B.A. 2 (Semester IV) Indian Logic

 B.A. 2 (Semester IV) Indian Logic



Indian Logic: Definition, Nature, and Scope

Indian logic, also known as Anviksiki, is a system of logic that has been developed and refined over centuries in India. It is a complex and sophisticated system that is based on a number of different philosophical and metaphysical assumptions.

Indian logic is often divided into two main branches: Nyaya and Vaisheshika. Nyaya is the branch of logic that is concerned with the study of inference and argumentation. Vaisheshika is the branch of logic that is concerned with the study of categories and ontology.

However, the distinction between Nyaya and Vaisheshika is not always clear-cut, and the two branches of Indian logic are often closely intertwined.

Nature of Indian Logic

Indian logic is a deductive system of logic. This means that it is concerned with the development of arguments that are logically valid. A logically valid argument is one in which the conclusion follows necessarily from the premises.

Indian logic is also a formal system of logic. This means that it is concerned with the logical structure of arguments, rather than their content. Indian logicians are interested in the logical relationships between propositions, rather than the truth or falsity of the propositions themselves.

Scope of Indian Logic

Indian logic has a very broad scope. It can be used to analyze and evaluate arguments in a wide range of fields, including philosophy, mathematics, science, and law.

Indian logic is also used in the study of Indian scriptures, such as the Vedas and the Upanishads. Indian logicians have developed a number of sophisticated techniques for interpreting and analyzing these texts.

Examples of Indian Logic

Here are a few examples of Indian logic:

  • Syllogism: A syllogism is a type of deductive argument that consists of three propositions: two premises and a conclusion. The premises are statements that are assumed to be true, and the conclusion is a statement that follows necessarily from the premises.

For example, the following is a syllogism:

* All humans are mortal.
* Socrates is a human.
* Therefore, Socrates is mortal.
  • Dilemma: A dilemma is a type of deductive argument that presents the opponent with two choices, each of which leads to an undesirable conclusion.

For example, the following is a dilemma:

* Either you support the war, or you support terrorism.
* Supporting the war is wrong.
* Supporting terrorism is wrong.
* Therefore, you are wrong.
  • Analogy: An analogy is a type of inductive argument that compares two or more things in order to draw a conclusion about one of the things.

For example, the following is an analogy:

* The heart is like a pump.
* A pump circulates blood.
* Therefore, the heart circulates blood.

Conclusion

Indian logic is a complex and sophisticated system of logic that has a wide range of applications. It is a valuable tool for anyone who wants to understand and evaluate arguments in a variety of fields.The nature of knowledge is a central question in philosophy. Epistemologists, or philosophers of knowledge, study the nature of knowledge, its origin, sources, scope, limitations, and its justification; its reliability or otherwise, and its certainty or otherwise.

There are many different theories about the nature of knowledge. Some of the most common theories include:

  • Foundationalism: Foundationalism is the view that knowledge is based on a foundation of self-evident truths. These self-evident truths are known directly and immediately, without the need for any evidence or justification.
  • Coherentism: Coherentism is the view that knowledge is justified by its coherence with other beliefs. A belief is justified if it is part of a coherent system of beliefs.
  • Empiricism: Empiricism is the view that all knowledge comes from experience. We learn about the world through our senses.
  • Rationalism: Rationalism is the view that knowledge comes from reason. We can learn about the world through thought and reflection, without the need for experience.

There are many other theories about the nature of knowledge, and there is no single theory that is universally accepted. The nature of knowledge is a complex and challenging question, and it is one that philosophers have been debating for centuries.

Here are some of the key features of knowledge:

  • Knowledge is justified. This means that there is good reason to believe that it is true.
  • Knowledge is true. This means that it corresponds to reality.
  • Knowledge is believed. This means that the person who has the knowledge believes it to be true.

It is important to note that knowledge is not necessarily certain. There are many things that we know, but that we are not absolutely certain about. For example, we know that the sun will rise tomorrow, but we are not absolutely certain about it. It is possible that the sun will not rise tomorrow, but it is extremely unlikely.

The nature of knowledge is a complex and fascinating topic. It is a topic that has been debated by philosophers for centuries. There is no single theory about the nature of knowledge that is universally accepted. However, there are some key features of knowledge that are widely agreed upon.Pramā (प्रमा) and Apramā (प्रमाण) are Sanskrit terms that refer to valid and invalid knowledge, respectively. They are important concepts in Indian epistemology, or the study of knowledge.

Pramā is defined as the right apprehension of an object. It is knowledge that is true and corresponds to reality. Apramā, on the other hand, is knowledge that is false and does not correspond to reality.

There are four main types of pramanas, or means of valid knowledge, in Indian epistemology:

  • Perception (pratyakṣa): Perception is the direct awareness of an object through the senses.
  • Inference (anumāna): Inference is the process of deriving knowledge about one thing from knowledge about another thing.
  • Comparison (upamāna): Comparison is the process of gaining knowledge about an object by comparing it to another object that is already known.
  • Verbal testimony (śabda): Verbal testimony is knowledge that is gained from the words of a reliable source.

Apramā, or invalid knowledge, can be caused by a variety of factors, such as:

  • Defects in the sense organs
  • Errors in reasoning
  • Bias or prejudice
  • Misleading testimony

The distinction between pramā and apramā is important because it helps us to evaluate our knowledge and to determine what is true and what is false. It also helps us to avoid making mistakes and to make better decisions.

Here are some examples of pramā and apramā:

Pramā:

  • Seeing a blue car.
  • Hearing a bird singing.
  • Feeling the heat of the sun.
  • Inferring that there is a fire because there is smoke.
  • Learning that the Earth is round from reading a scientific textbook.

Apramā:

  • Mistaking a mirage for a lake.
  • Hearing a noise and thinking it is a ghost.
  • Feeling pain in a limb that has been amputated.
  • Inferring that it is going to rain because the sky is cloudy.
  • Believing that the Earth is flat because a religious text says so.

It is important to note that the distinction between pramā and apramā is not always clear-cut. In some cases, it can be difficult to determine whether or not a piece of knowledge is valid. This is why it is important to be critical of our knowledge and to carefully evaluate the sources of our information.Nature of Pramāṇa

Pramāṇa, a Sanskrit word, literally means "means of knowledge". It encompasses one or more reliable and valid means by which human beings gain accurate, true knowledge. The Nyaya school of Hinduism accepts four means of obtaining knowledge (pramāṇa), viz., Perception, Inference, Comparison and Word. Perception, called Pratyakṣa, occupies the foremost position in the Nyaya epistemology. Perception is defined by sense-object contact and is unerring.

Different kinds of Pramāṇa

The four kinds of pramāṇa are:

  • Perception (Pratyakṣa): Perception is the direct knowledge of an object through the senses. It is the most fundamental and reliable means of knowledge, according to the Nyaya school.
  • Inference (Anumāna): Inference is the knowledge of an object that is not directly perceptible, but is inferred from the presence of another object that is perceptible. For example, we infer the presence of fire from the presence of smoke.
  • Comparison (Upamāna): Comparison is the knowledge of an object by comparing it to another object that is already known. For example, we compare a red rose to another red rose and conclude that they are both red.
  • Word (Śabda): Word is the knowledge of an object that is gained from the testimony of a reliable source. For example, we believe in the existence of God because of the testimony of the scriptures.

Perception according to Nyāya

The Nyaya school defines perception as the direct knowledge of an object through the senses. It is a valid means of knowledge because it is immediate, unerring, and self-evident. Perception can be of two types: ordinary and extraordinary.

Ordinary perception (Laukika or Sādhārana) is the perception of objects through the six senses: sight, hearing, smell, taste, touch, and mind.

Extraordinary perception (Alaukika or Asādhārana) is the perception of objects that are beyond the reach of the six senses. It includes clairvoyance, clairaudience, and telepathy.

The Nyaya school also distinguishes between two types of perceptual knowledge:

  • Sense-object contact (Saṁyoga): This is the direct contact of the sense organ with the object of perception. For example, when we see a red rose, the photons of light from the rose come into contact with our eyes.
  • Apprehension (Avachheda): This is the awareness of the object of perception. For example, when we see a red rose, we are aware of its color, shape, and size.

The Nyaya school also discusses the various factors that can affect perception, such as:

  • Distance: Objects that are further away are more difficult to perceive than objects that are closer.
  • Size: Smaller objects are more difficult to perceive than larger objects.
  • Light: Objects that are in the light are easier to perceive than objects that are in the dark.
  • Bias: Our preconceived notions and biases can affect our perception of objects.

Despite these factors, the Nyaya school maintains that perception is a valid means of knowledge because it is the most direct and immediate way to know the world around us.Inference according to Nyāya

Inference, or anumāna, is one of the four valid means of knowledge in Nyāya epistemology. It is defined as the knowledge of an object that is not directly perceptible, but is inferred from the presence of another object that is perceptible. For example, we infer the presence of fire from the presence of smoke.

The Nyaya school of Hinduism identifies five steps in the inferential process:

  1. Pratijñā: The proposition to be proven. For example, "There is fire on the hill."
  2. Hetu: The middle term, or reason, for the proposition. For example, "There is smoke on the hill."
  3. Udāharaṇa: The major premise, which is a general statement about the relationship between the middle term and the conclusion. For example, "Wherever there is smoke, there is fire."
  4. Upanaya: The minor premise, which applies the major premise to the specific case at hand. For example, "The hill has smoke."
  5. Nigamana: The conclusion, which follows logically from the premises. For example, "Therefore, there is fire on the hill."

Inference according to Buddhism

The Buddhist tradition also recognizes inference as a valid means of knowledge. However, the Buddhist analysis of inference differs from the Nyaya analysis in several ways.

First, the Buddhist tradition does not accept the Nyaya distinction between ordinary and extraordinary perception. According to the Buddhist tradition, all perception is mental. This means that even our direct experience of the world is mediated by our minds.

Second, the Buddhist tradition does not accept the Nyaya view of the relationship between the middle term and the conclusion of an inference. According to the Nyaya tradition, the middle term is a sign of the conclusion. However, according to the Buddhist tradition, the middle term is simply a reason for believing the conclusion. This means that inferences can be false, even if the middle term is true.

Inference according to Jainism

The Jain tradition also recognizes inference as a valid means of knowledge. However, the Jain analysis of inference is similar to the Nyaya analysis in several ways.

First, the Jain tradition accepts the Nyaya distinction between ordinary and extraordinary perception.

Second, the Jain tradition accepts the Nyaya view of the relationship between the middle term and the conclusion of an inference. According to the Jain tradition, the middle term is a sign of the conclusion. However, the Jain tradition also emphasizes the importance of logical rigor in the inferential process.

Overall, the three traditions of Nyaya, Buddhism, and Jainism all recognize inference as a valid means of knowledge. However, there are some important differences in their analyses of inference.Verbal Testimony (Śabda)

Verbal testimony is the knowledge of an object that is gained from the testimony of a reliable source. It is a valid means of knowledge because it is based on the assumption that reliable people will not tell lies.

Examples of verbal testimony include:

  • The testimony of experts: We believe that the Earth is round because of the testimony of scientists.
  • The testimony of our elders: We believe that our ancestors came from India because of the testimony of our parents and grandparents.
  • The testimony of scriptures: Hindus believe in the existence of God because of the testimony of the Vedas.

Upamāna (Comparison)

Comparison is the knowledge of an object by comparing it to another object that is already known. It is a valid means of knowledge because it is based on the assumption that similar objects have similar properties.

Examples of comparison include:

  • We compare a red rose to another red rose and conclude that they are both red.
  • We compare a dog to a cat and conclude that they are both mammals.
  • We compare the current economic crisis to the Great Depression and conclude that they are both serious economic problems.

Arthāpatti (Postulation)

Postulation is the knowledge of an object that is inferred from the necessity of the case. It is a valid means of knowledge because it is based on the assumption that what is necessary must exist.

Examples of postulation include:

  • We see a pot with water boiling and infer that there must be fire underneath it.
  • We see a cloudless sky and infer that there must be no rain.
  • We see a person who is always working hard and infer that they must be successful.

Anupalabdhi (Non-Apprehension)

Non-apprehension is the knowledge of the absence of an object based on the failure to perceive it. It is a valid means of knowledge because it is based on the assumption that what is not perceived does not exist.

Examples of non-apprehension include:

  • We look for a pot in the kitchen and do not find it. We infer that the pot must not be in the kitchen.
  • We look for a cat in the garden and do not find it. We infer that the cat must not be in the garden.
  • We look for a unicorn in the forest and do not find it. We infer that unicorns must not exist.

It is important to note that all four of these means of knowledge are accepted by some schools of Indian philosophy, but not by all. For example, the Buddhist tradition does not accept the validity of verbal testimony, while the Nyaya tradition does not accept the validity of non-apprehension.

Overall, the four means of knowledge discussed above are important tools for understanding the world around us. They allow us to gain knowledge about things that we cannot directly perceive, and to make inferences about the world based on the knowledge that we do have.Prāmāṇyavāda is a branch of Indian philosophy that deals with the nature of knowledge and the means by which we can acquire it. In Prāmāṇyavāda, there are two main schools of thought on the source of knowledge: svataḥ prāmāṇyavāda and parataḥ prāmāṇyavāda.

Svataḥ prāmāṇyavāda is the view that knowledge is self-evident and does not require any external justification. According to this view, knowledge is simply the apprehension of an object by the senses or the mind. For example, when we see a red rose, we simply apprehend the redness of the rose. This knowledge does not need to be justified by any external source, such as a teacher or a scripture.

Parataḥ prāmāṇyavāda is the view that knowledge requires external justification. According to this view, knowledge is not simply the apprehension of an object, but also the understanding of the object. For example, when we see a red rose, we not only apprehend the redness of the rose, but we also understand that it is a rose. This understanding requires external justification, such as the testimony of a teacher or a scripture.

Arguments for Svataḥ Prāmāṇyavāda

Proponents of svataḥ prāmāṇyavāda argue that knowledge is self-evident because it is immediate and direct. When we see a red rose, we simply apprehend the redness of the rose. This apprehension does not require any external justification, because it is simply the awareness of the object.

Arguments for Parataḥ Prāmāṇyavāda

Proponents of parataḥ prāmāṇyavāda argue that knowledge requires external justification because it is not simply the apprehension of an object, but also the understanding of the object. For example, when we see a red rose, we not only apprehend the redness of the rose, but we also understand that it is a rose. This understanding requires external justification, such as the testimony of a teacher or a scripture.

Conclusion

The debate between svataḥ prāmāṇyavāda and parataḥ prāmāṇyavāda is a complex one that has been debated by Indian philosophers for centuries. There are strong arguments to be made on both sides of the issue, and ultimately, each individual must decide which view they find more convincing.Khyātivāda is a Sanskrit term that means "theories of error." It is a branch of Indian philosophy that deals with the nature of error and the causes of illusory perception. There are many different theories of error in Indian philosophy, but they can be broadly divided into two categories:

  • Asatkhyātivāda: This theory holds that error is the perception of the non-existent. For example, when we see a mirage in the desert, we are mistaking a non-existent body of water for a real one.
  • Satkhyātivāda: This theory holds that error is the misperception of the existent. For example, when we see a yellow conch shell in the twilight, we are mistaking its yellow color for white.

Within these two broad categories, there are many different theories of error that have been proposed by different Indian philosophers. For example, the Buddhist school of Madhyamaka holds that error is the result of our clinging to the inherent existence of things, which is ultimately an illusion. The Jain school of philosophy, on the other hand, holds that error is the result of our ignorance of the true nature of things.

Causes of illusory perception

Indian philosophers have also proposed a variety of different causes of illusory perception. Some of the most common causes include:

  • Defects in the senses: Our senses can be deceived by certain conditions, such as low light or fatigue. For example, if we are looking at a distant object in the twilight, we may mistake it for something else.
  • Mental defects: Our minds can also be deceived by certain conditions, such as emotions or prejudice. For example, if we are afraid of snakes, we may mistake a harmless stick for a snake.
  • Defects in the object of perception: The object of perception itself can also be defective. For example, a mirage is a defect of the atmosphere, not of our senses.

Conclusion

The theories of error in Indian philosophy are complex and sophisticated. They provide us with a deep understanding of the nature of perception and the causes of illusory perception. These theories are still relevant today, and they can help us to better understand our own cognitive processes.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Writing skill development on topics of Contemporary Sociological Importance

Social Problems &Issues of Development in India BA 2 nd Year, Sem. IV , Course I (Theory)

Classical Sociological Thought BA 3 rd Year, Sem. V , Course I (Theory) Programme /Class Degree Year B.A III Semester V Subject Sociology Course code A070501T Course